Open Side Menu Go to the Top
Register
The Sociological Imagination The Sociological Imagination

04-12-2019 , 05:17 PM
That is the title of a 1959 book by the sociologist C Wright Mills. As the wiki will tell you, it's common for intro Sociology classes to use that phrase to introduce sociology and try to explain what it is and why anyone should care about it. That seems like a good place to start to me as well, although I don't intend to actually reference that particular text very much.

Here's a good summary from a professor at Cornell:

Quote:
C. Wright Mills defined the sociological imagination as "the vivid awareness of the relationship between personal experience and the wider society" (1959:6). It enables us to "grasp history and biography and the relations between the two within society" (1959:6). In other words, it is the ability to understand how personal experiences are shaped by historically-conditioned social forces. You are your own person with your own story (biography), but you are influenced in a million ways by the social structure and people who came before you (history). Sociology is going to challenge you to think about how we fit into the “bigger picture” of society, and all of its complexities. The sociological perspective views human behavior as “mediated, shaped, channeled, and influenced by social relationships and social systems (Johnson et al. 2006: ).”
It's a good place to start because a lot of what makes social sciences contentious, IMO, is in the way they tend to challenge common beliefs about the relationship between supposed dichotomies of "nature" and "nurture", (social) "structure" and (individual) "agency" (see the link above), Individualism and Collectivism (as political philosophies), and so on. So, to start from the very beginning, I would argue that the importance of "the sociological imagination" comes first of all from the fact that human beings are social beings, and that our sociality is intrinsic to our nature. Therefore, any deep understanding of human behavior must account for those social qualities, and overly reductionistic accounts of human behavior which try to subordinate the social with the individual are very likely to fail.

Here are a few of my favorite social scientists:

Quote:
The Enlightenment view of man was, of course, that he was wholly of a piece with nature and shared in the general uniformity of composition which natural science, under Bacon's urging and Newton's guidance, had discovered there. There is, in brief, a human nature as regularly organized, as thoroughly invariant, and as marvelously simple as Newton's universe. Perhaps some of its laws are different, but there are laws; perhaps some of its immutability is obscured by the trappings of local fashion, but it is immutable....

Now, this view is hardly one to be despised; nor, despite my easy references a moment ago to "overthrow," can it be said to have disappeared from contemporary anthropological thought. The notion that men are men under whatever guise and against whatever backdrop has not been replaced by "other mores, other beasts."

Thus, in a passage now notorious, Dr. Johnson saw Shakespeare's genius to lie in the fact that "his characters are not modified by the customs of particular places, unpractised by the rest of the world; by the peculiarities of studies or professions, which can operate upon but small numbers; or by the accidents of transient fashions or temporary opinions." And Racine regarded the success of his plays on classical themes as proof that "the taste of Paris . . . conforms to that of Athens; my spectators have been moved by the same things which, in other times, brought tears to the eyes of the most cultivated classes of Greece."

The trouble with this kind of view, aside from the fact that it sounds comic coming from someone as profoundly English as Johnson or as French as Racine, is that the image of a constant human nature independent of time, place, and circumstance, of studies and professions, transient fashions and temporary opinions, may be an illusion, that what man is may be so entangled with where he is, who he is, and what he believes that it is inseparable from them. It is precisely the consideration of such a possibility that led to the rise of the concept of culture and the decline of the uniformitarian view of man. Whatever else modern anthropology asserts--and it seems to have asserted almost everything at one time or another--it is firm in the conviction that men unmodified by the customs of particular places do not in fact exist, have never existed, and most important, could not in the very nature of the case exist. There is, there can be, no backstage where we can go to catch a glimpse of Mascou's actors as "real persons" lounging about in street clothes, disengaged from their profession, displaying with artless candor their spontaneous desires and unprompted passions. They may change their roles, their styles of acting, even the dramas in which they play; but--as Shakespeare himself of course remarked--they are always performing.

This circumstance makes the drawing of a line between what is natural, universal, and constant in man and what is conventional, local, and variable extraordinarily difficult. In fact, it suggests that to draw such a line is to falsify the human situation, or at least to misrender it seriously.
-- Clifford Geertz, "The Impact of the Concept of Culture on the Concept of Man" (The Interpretation of Cultures, 1973, pp. 34-6)

Quote:
Man's self-production is always, and of necessity, a social enterprise. Men together produce a human environment, with the totality of its socio-cultural and psychological formations. None of these formations may be understood as products of man's biological constitution, which, as indicated, provides only the outer limits for human productive activity. Just as it is impossible for man to develop as man in isolation, so it is impossible for man in isolation to produce a human environment. Solitary human being is being on the animal level (which, of course, man shares with other animals). As soon as one observes phenomena that are specifically human, one enters the realm of the social. Man's specific humanity and his sociality are inextricably intertwined. **** Sapiens is always, and in the same measure, **** socius.
-- Berger and Luckmann, The Social Construction of Reality (1966, p. 51)

Berger and Luckmann might seem to overstate things a little when they write that "none of these formations may be understood as products of man's biological constitution", but bear in mind they don't mean there is no relation whatsoever between human biology and behavior, they just mean that the latter cannot be reduced to the former, nor can the collectivity of human behavior be reduced to a simple aggregation of individual psychology.

For a more modern empirical take on the intrinsically social nature of distinctive human being, see for example Becoming Human: A Theory of Ontogeny.

What "The sociological imagination" first aims to do then, is to make clear the importance of understanding sociality to understanding humanity. Berger and Luckmann go on to develop a theory of the sociology of knowledge (how is human knowledge produced?) which elaborates in a general way on what this means, which I'll briefly outline next.
The Sociological Imagination Quote
04-12-2019 , 06:07 PM
In The Social Construction of Reality, Berger and Luckmann conceptualize the "production of a human environment" mentioned above as process in which three "moments" interact with each other in an on-going way (they use the technical term dialectic, but we can ignore that).

Those moments are externalization, objectification, and internalization. They write about knowledge, but I think this conceptual framework is a useful general way to think about the relationship between the individual and culture.

Externalization means, very simply, that we create things through our being. Physical artifacts, but also ideas, language, art, and so on. We're always going on producing things. But the things which we produce do not remain confined to our individual minds -- not even the ideas. Through social interactions they come to have a kind of objective (or at least intersubjective) existence. This becomes especially clear over the course of generations, because for the young the collective knowledge and beliefs of parents are understood explicitly in an "objective" way (cf. Becoming Human on this point). But, that is not the end of the story, because those "out there" ideas are also internalized by us, and in the process modified, re-externalized in our new beliefs and behavior, re-objectified, and so on.

Berger and Luckmann analyze the process of objectification with the help of a few different concepts. The first is Habitualization, which provides a means of understanding the sociological concept of an "institution":

Quote:
All human activity is subject to habitualization. Any action that is repeated frequently becomes cast into a pattern, which can then be reproduced with an economy of effort and which, ipso facto, is apprehended by its performer as that action. Habitualization further implies that the action in question may be performed again in the future in the same manner and with the same economical effort.... While in theory there may be a hundred ways to go about the project of building a canoe out of matchsticks, habitualization narrows these down to one....

Institutionalization occurs whenever there is a reciprocal typification of habitualized actions by types of actors. Put differently, any such typification is an institution. What must be stressed is the reciprocity of institutional and the typicality of not only the actions but also the actors in institutions (p.53-4)
The book, of course, goes into more detail, but I think the simple concept is hopefully evocative enough. The point is that the habitualization of activities and specifically the knowledge associated with those habits ("how to plant a garden"; "how to fix a flat tire"; ...) is a human product, and in the process of sharing that knowledge with others it comes to take on a more concrete existence, such that when young children acquire knowledge of this sort they not only understand it as "this is one way to do this" but as "this is how one ought to do this" (cf. Becoming Human). We have evolved this tendency to institutionalize knowledge and give it a normative dimension because it facilitates social cohesion.

As Berger and Luckmann mention, it's not just patterns of action which become habitualized and then institutionalized, but also expectations that certain types of individuals are the ones who properly perform those same actions. This is the sociological concept of a Role. Think for example of gendered expectations in many societies about which types of activities are suitable for men and women. It may be a man's role to change the flat tire and a woman's role to cook dinner, at least in some cultures. These sorts of stereotypical expectations become externalized and objectified just as the knowledge of how to do those tasks is institutionalized. This applies to almost every aspect of human social existence.

In relation to the sociological imagination then, the point here is that if you want to understand how a person acts, what she thinks, and so on it will be necessary to understand how institutions and roles are constructed within her culture ("structure"), and not just her individual beliefs and preferences ("agency'). This is because our individual beliefs and actions are clearly shaped by these external structures, even in very mundane ways, and we attach significance and meaning to those roles and patterns of behavior that go far beyond simply understanding them as "one way out of many". We internalize socially produced knowledge.

Understanding the meaning we attach to behavior leads then to the concept of Legitimation, which is important in Berger and Luckmann's account.

One potential limitation of focusing on the development of institutions, roles, norms, beliefs and so on via a process that flows in one direction, from externalization to objectification, is that it will lead to a very static picture of culture or social organization. But clearly all these things are in constant flux. In this theory, that is accounted for by the feedback loop between internalization and (re)-externalization. We are also always engaged in processes of renegotiating all of these things: knowledge, roles, institutions, and so on. But there is clearly an interesting kind of stability here as well. We don't instantly abandon all of the beliefs of our parents.

Legitimation, then, describes the processes by which existing social structures are defended. Alongside the production of the knowledge
1) "how to do X"
and the belief that
2) "role Y should do X",
a very similar process leads to the production of explanations for
3) why is it right that X should be done this way by Y?
Those explanations are "legitimations". Berger made great use of this framework for investigating religious legitimations in particular, which tend to try to make such explanations metaphysically absolute: "It is right to do X because [God wills it] or [it is according to our fundamental nature]" and so on.

My hope is that thinking about these very general theoretical considerations will help make clearer the value of "the sociological imagination" to understanding human existence, and why "structural" approaches to understanding human behavior have something to contribute beyond approaches which interrogate individual psychology in isolation.
The Sociological Imagination Quote

      
m